0
Generative AI has recently become available to the general public via web browsers, making the experience of âcreatingââor in the context of this dossier âco-creatingââa seemingly novel image (or text or, most recently, video) accessible to everyone who is capable of typing and has an internet connection. This sort of ease to âcreateâ something with a high degree of technical accuracy has appeared before: the photographic apparatus of the camera.
1
In his treatise Towards a Philosophy of Photography, the Czech-Brazilian philosopher VilĂ©m Flusser carries out an in-depth analysis of the relationship between the photographer, the camera, and the universe of images it generates. The case study of the camera is intended to also serve as a âgeneral analysis of apparatus[es].â1 âApparatusâ can be understood as an âoverarching term for a non-human agency, e.g. the camera, the computer and the âapparatusâ of the State or of the market.â2 Apparatuses are complex systems distributed across many componentsâboth mechanical and social, hard and soft technologies.
In Flusserâs analysis, âall apparatuses (not just computers) are calculating machines and in this sense [are] âartificial intelligences,â the camera included, even if their inventors were not able to account for this.â3 Thus, Flusserâs examination of the dynamic that exists between the camera (the photographic apparatus) and the photographer (whom he calls the âfunctionaryâ) can be fruitful when considering the dynamic between generative AI systems like DALL-E, Midjourney, and Stable Diffusion, and their human users (the âfunctionariesâ).
While the camera is a literal black box, the apparatus is a figurative black box; this is an essential characteristic of its functioning. As Flusser wrote, âthe functionary controls the apparatus thanks to the control of its exterior (the input and output) and is controlled by it thanks to the impenetrability of its interior.â4 For Flusser, the photographer serves (and âis controlled byâ) the cameraâthe functionary serves the apparatusâand operates within the predetermined rules, or âprogramâ, of the apparatus, which he defines as âa combination game with clear and distinct elements.â5 In this sense, the person who operates the apparatus becomes a function of its program.
Flusser discerns two intertwined programs within the camera: one that enables the camera’s technical operation, and another that provides the photographer with a âlanguageâ of images to explore.6 However, these programs are not isolated. The camera is also part of a larger network, affected by the programs of the photographic industry that designed it. This industry, in turn, is influenced by the broader industrial complex which is itself shaped by the socio-economic system. In this hierarchy of programs, which Flusser describes as being âopen at the top,â7 the functionary’s agency is minimal. Their sense of freedom is merely a âprogrammed freedomâ within the predetermined parameters of this hierarchy of programs and the âphotographic universeâ.8
Towards what, if anything, or into what, if anything, does this hierarchy open?
2
The word apparatus is sometimes applied to natural phenomena. Flusser gives the example of an animalâs hearing apparatus. For Flusser, such usage is âmetaphoricalâ though, and amounts to âapplying a cultural term to the natural world,â and âif there were no apparatuses in our culture, we should not refer to such organs in that way.â9
This is a recurring pattern of interpreting natural systems through cultural frameworks. Philosopher RenĂ© Descartes conceived of animals as machines in the 17th century, a moment in a long lineage of thinking going back to ancient Greece and extending into the present that leads to contemporary biological engineeringâthe application of engineering principles to living organisms.
In his book The Selfish Gene, evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins argues that genes are the fundamental units of natural selection and that organismsâwhich Darwin had defined as the unit of selection a century beforeâare mere “survival machines” for these genes.
From this perspective, and through adopting the language of Flusser in a metaphorical way, we could say that organisms are both the survival machines and the functionaries within the genetic universe.
3
The notion of âgenerativeâ has a biological etymology related to reproduction. The sheer fecundity and ease of access to generative AI in both image and text have grabbed headlines and filled social media feeds. However, there is another guise of AI operating more quietly and away from the mass audiences of social media. This AI will impact the future of another, ontologically different, generative domain: biological life. By leveraging advances in computational power, data analysis, and machine learning techniques, AI is opening vast new potentials to create, among other developments, novel biological organisms.
In the metaphorical conceptualisation of organisms as âfunctionariesâ within the âapparatusâ of life, it would seem that life has found a new âfunctionaryâ in the human-AI coupled systemâa functionary that can radically expand the scope and pace of exploration of the possibilities of the genetic universe.
Scientific researchers have already used artificial intelligence to create so-called âxenobots,â which are living, reproducing ârobotsâ from frog stem cells.10 The conceptualisation of life as machinic (from Descartes to Dawkins to bio-engineering) has led to biological machines becoming a reality. Thus, in the end, life as machine is not a metaphor but a hyperstition.11
Writing in the early 1980s, Flusser observed that âthe technical images currently all around us are in the process of magically restructuring our ârealityâ and turning it into a âglobal image scenarioâ.â12 When Flusser makes reference to a âmagical relationshipâ he means a break with historical relationships: as the âgaze wanders over the surfaceâ of âthe photograph, rather than seeing historical events with their causes and consequences, we see magical connections.â13
Both Earth and biological life are historical systems. The (interconnected) feedback loop between organism and environment is essential for the propagation of life across time. Where artificial selection started to bend this relationship, genetic engineering and synthetic biology have broken this historical relationship. In the same way that photography replaced a historical relationship with a magical relationship, as discussed above, synthetic biology augmented by AI will give life a magical rather than historical relationship to time. Without any recourse to environment or history (the consequences of) artificial intelligence in biology will establish new relationships that entirely break with history. AI will explore the âchemical spaceâ (or we could say âchemical universeâ) of entirely different hereditary molecular systems besides DNA.14 One can imagine the etymological origin of âgenerativeââfrom the Proto-Indo-European root “give birth, beget”âwill return when the life sciences deploy their own forms of generative AI.15
The accelerating climate crisis and environmental change has started a sixth mass extinction,16 with the speed of change becoming too rapid for many organisms to adapt. Will the “survival machines” of genes that biological generative AI engenders be among those that repopulate the Earth? Where will that ultimately leave the human progenitors of AI?
4
Flusser’s concept of the camera suggests that it must have a complex program; otherwise, âthe game would soon be over.â17 The potential capabilities built into it must exceed the ability of the operator to fully utilize them, implying that the camera’s program should surpass that of its functionaries. Flusser writes that âno photographer, not even the totality of all photographers, can entirely get to the bottom of what a correctly programmed camera is up to. It is a black box.”18 This notion extends beyond photography to our wider discourse on AI and life systems.
The images in this contribution to the research dossier are glimpses suggesting possible futures in which this process continuesâin which living organisms are no longer metaphorically but actually biological machines in an AI-augmented approach to biological engineering. Rephrasing Flusserâs description of the feedback loop between the photographer and the camera as a description of the relationship between biological engineering and life in the near future, it could be said that as the AI-coupled bioengineer functionary controls the apparatus of life, it too is controlled by the apparatus of life. The design of artificial intelligence systemsâoften described as black boxesâhas, after all, not only been created by living organisms but has leaned on (the human, scientific understanding of) living systems, from evolutionary algorithms to neural networks.
Life is an even blacker box. The functionaries of life cannot exhaust the program of lifeâthey can never get to the bottom of what life is up toânor to the top of the open hierarchy of programs.
5
These images, which are interspersed throughout this text, have been produced with the generative AI platform Midjourney. Within the schema Flusser has set out, I have served merely as a functionary. These images and my production of them are not intended to either endorse or condone the hyperstitional process elaborated above, but rather to bring it into the conversation about AI co-creation. That conversation is currently dominated by text and image-based generative-AI, which grabs headlines and is highly visible on social media, yet biological life is being much more quietly transformed by AI and that conversation remains nascent, even as it poses a far greater impact on not only future human societies but indeed on the future of all life.
References
↥1 | VilĂ©m Flusser. Towards a Philosophy of Photography London: Reaktion Books, 2013, p.21. |
↥2 | ibid. p.83. |
↥3 | ibid. p.31. |
↥4 | ibid. p.28. |
↥5 | ibid. p.84. |
↥6 | ibid. p.29. |
↥7 | ibid. p.29 |
↥8 | ibid. p.35. |
↥9 | ibid. p.22. |
↥10 | For more information see âThese Researchers Used AI to Design a Completely New ‘Animal Robotâ or âLiving robots made in a lab have found a new way to self-replicate, researchers sayâ |
↥11 | Hyperstitions are things which, according to philosopher Nick Land, âby their very existence as ideas â function causally to bring about their own reality.â Delphi Carstens and Land, Nick (2009). âHyperstition: An Introduction: Delphi Carstens interviews Nick Landâ. Orphan Drift. |
↥12 | VilĂ©m Flusser. Towards a Philosophy of Photography London: Reaktion Books, 2013, p.71. |
↥13 | ibid., p.60. |
↥14 | See the work of Henderson James Cleaves III et al., âOne Among Millions: The Chemical Space of Nucleic Acid-Like Molecules,â in Journal of Chemical Information and Modeling, vol. 59, no. 10, 2019. This point is also summarized clearly in âDNA is only one among millions of possible genetic molecules,â Science Daily. |
↥15 | âgenerative (adj.),â etymology, Online Etymology Dictonary. |
↥16 | See âEarth’s sixth mass extinction event under way, scientists warnâ for more information about the sixth mass extinction |
↥17 | VilĂ©m Flusser. Towards a Philosophy of Photography London: Reaktion Books, 2013, p.27. |
↥18 | ibid., p.27. |